Introduction
to a Dialectical Theory of Political Economy based on Dialectical
Contradictions.
Raymond
Swing (2010)
Keywords:
Marx, classical and post-classical theory, value, labour-power, exchange.
1. Peter Ruben’s
logical definition of value-un-decidedness.
In his book Dialektik und Arbeit der Philosophie (1978)[1]
Peter Ruben offers a logical analysis of the so-called „dialectical
contradiction“ starting out from the formal judgement building, negations and
counternegations, thereby using the common logical signs: ! meaning “it is
true that…”, Ø
“it is not true that…”, Î
“is”, p its predicative, ~
“not”, Ù
sentence conjunction and & the predicative conjunction and finally Û
for bi-implication indicating equivalence.
Now
Peter Ruben takes two predicative sentences (S):
!S/Îp
and !S/Î~p
which when taken together build the sentence conjunction
!S/Îp Ù !S/Î~p
(‘it is true that S is p and it is true that
S is non-p‘), the standard example of the logical value false. By means of the affirmative paradox (‘it is both
true that p and non-p’) we then
define the logical contradiction (Cdlog.)
by the following bi-implication:
(1)
!S/Î(p
& ~p) Î Cdlog.
=df !S/Î(p
& ~p) Û
!S/Îp
Ù
!S/Î~p.
So the
affirmative paradox as a positive judgement exactly represents the logical
contradiction in so far it can be stated logically equivalent to !S/Îp Ù
!S/Î~p.
To this Peter Ruben in his paper has this comment: “Whether this is the case
is to be determined in the frame of the presupposed theory. It can not be stated
a priori” (Ibid., p.141; all transl. R.S.).
Now, using
the difference between “outer” (Ø)
and “inner Negations” (~) we have at our disposal both negation and counter-affirmation so that
we can negate the original (false)
sentence conjunction !S/Îp
Ù
!S/Î~p
and so create the new: ØS/Îp
Ù
ØS/Î~p
; this one as the negation of false,
however – and that is the crux of the matter – cannot mean true but in fact logically generates a third value. Again Peter
Ruben:
Of
course, this is no work of predication but rather the product of a value
formation which you also could express by using the predicative “value-un-decided”.
We call the corresponding logical term “logical un-decidedness”. (Ibid.,
p.141).
From this
logical argument Ruben finally defines the “dialectical contradiction” (Cddial)
in this way:
(2)
!S/Î(p
& ~p) Î Cddial.
=df !S/Î(p
& ~p) Û
ØS/Îp
Ù
ØS/Î~p.
An
affirmative paradox exactly represents a dialectic contradiction if the positive
judgement about this affirmative paradox is logically equivalent to the term of
logical un-desidedness. In other words: the dialectic contradiction appears logically
as un-decidedness. (Ibid.,
p.142).
On the other
hand, in the frame of formal logic Ruben finally states that
(3)
ØS/Îp
Ù
ØS/Î~p
Þ
Ø(!S/Îp
Ù
!S/Î~p).
In
the language of the formal logic this theorem says: The dialectical
contradiction involves the exclusion of the logical contradiction. In the
language of analytics this means: The dialectical contradiction is the
sufficient condition for excluding the logical contradiction; the exclusion the
logical contradiction is the necessary condition for the existence of the
dialectical contradiction. In the language of Hegel this theorem says: The
dialectical contradiction sets the logical contradiction. (Ibid.)
And Peter
Ruben concludes his paper on predication with the words:
He
who wants the logical version of the dialectical contradiction contrarily to the
logical one must accept the existence of logical un-decidedness! (In respect to
the negative paradox there is no un-decidedness; therefore this one cannot give
any dialectical contradiction.) He who excludes any un-decidedness will newer
clear up the dialectics. (Ibid.)
With
these arguments Peter Ruben clearly opposes Aristotle’s metaphysical ontology
where the copula is just separates the
sentence subject from its predicative(s), that is, takes them in separation one
by one only connected by the copula is.
Contrarily to this Peter Ruben states subject and predicative(s) to be different,
but inseparable, i.e. existing only as members of the content-bearing sentences
which according to classical logic as judgements must be either true or false (Tertium
non datur). However, on this basis now including the “logical
un-decidedness” and consequently the logical definition of the dialectical
contradiction, this classical principle can no longer be maintained as a
generally accepted truth (Tertium datur!).
In the sense of his dialectic ontology
(“ontology is no metaphysics but the doctrine about what sentences and their
members really means”, p. 122) he states as his guiding rule:
Subjects
indicate things, predicates properties, their unities, the sentences, are
expressions of matters of fact. There are no properties without things (bearers)
and no things without properties. So subjects and predicates are inseparable;
they indicate dialectic opposites of contradictions which themselves are
sentences. The term “matter of fact” [Sachverhalt]
is just to be understood indicating the concrete unity of a fact (a thing) and
its behaviour (its property). This means that a sentence is the expression of a
concrete unity and its members as subject and predicate signs of the this unity
conditioning opposites. (Ibid., p.
121f)
2. Contradictions in
the concept of the commodities.
The real philosophical problem is now descriptively to indicate such objects
characterised by an
affirmative paradox
equivalent to (bi-implicating) the term of logical un-decidedness which so to
say characterises these objects’ outer conditions, that is, the double
conditions of their existence the poles of which they have to unify and about
which Marx says, that this ‘does not abolish these contradictions but rather
provides the form within they have room to move’ (cf. Capital
I, p. 198). In this connection some school-examples shall be discussed here,
commodities on the market and the concept of “labour power” realising
“living labour” under the conditions of capitalist economy. Among other
things we shall therefore demonstrate the logical un-decidedness of the market
function (the circulation sphere) under the condition of functioning of
workshops (the production sphere). Further cases will be discussed in analogue
ways.
Karl
Marx’s Capital I takes its point of
departure by analysing the nature of the commodity as we find them on the market.
Traditionally we characterise this as the unity of: being both “value” and
“use-value” which can be interpreted as an affirmatively paradox in so far
use-value can be identified as non-value. Let us call value
p
and consequently use-value
in the sense of being non-value ~p
. Then we can descriptively define the commodity
C by the predicative-conjunction
!C/Î(p
& ~p). But let us quote Marx
himself:
If
then we disregard the use-value of commodities, only one property remains, that
of being products of labour. (…) If we make abstraction from its use-value, we
abstract also from the material constituents and forms making up the use-value.
It is no longer a table, a house, a piece of yarn or any other useful thing. All
its sensuous characteristics are extinguished. Nor is it any longer the product
of the labour of the joiner, the mason or the spinner, or of any particular kind
of productive labour. With the disappearance of the useful character of the
products of labour, the useful character of the kinds of labour embodied in them
also disappears; this in turn entails the disappearance of the different
concrete forms of labour. They can no longer be distinguished, but are all
together reduced to the same kind of labour, human labour in abstract. (Capital
I, p. 128)
When having
in mind that as well value as use-value are products of concrete living labour
over time, this quotation indicates that value in abstract cannot be exactly
determined in any descriptive way in the case of commodities (C)
staying on the market which cannot be determined under these conditions; so we
state: ØC/Îp
(‘the different
concrete forms of labour’ disappear when reduced to an amount of time once in
the past). On the other hand: also indicating the use-value in abstract is
according to this negated: ØC/Î~p
(‘the useful character of the kinds of labour embodied in them also disappears’);
use-value is only a matter of concrete use after the commodity has once been
bought in the future. Consequently, when value and use-value is taken in
separation, in abstract as matters of past and future, there remains only
logical un-decidedness expressed with the term
ØC/Îp
Ù
ØC/Î~p
equivalent to the affirmative paradox
!C/Î(p
& ~p). That is, we have in a
descriptive way reproduced the dialectical contradiction contained in
commodities in general as long as they are staying on the market:
(4)
!C/Î(p
& ~p) Û
ØC/Îp
Ù
ØC/Î~p .
On the other
hand, we must not undertake the logical shortcut cancelling the affirmative
paradox saying: the commodity as such is
value and also is use-value: !C/Îp
Ù
!C/Î~p .
This would exactly separate
the logical predicatives and according to formula 1 above generate a logical
contradiction.
3.
‘Contradictions in the Formula
for Capital’. Peter
Ruben’s above given deduction of the dialectical contradiction could very well
have been conceived on the basis of Karl Marx’s chapter 5 of his Capital
I, Contradictions in the Formula for Capital, so that this Marxian
argument could be taken as a further school example of dialectical
contradictions. Marx takes his point of departure in the well-known formula
M-C-M’ (money, commodity, more money; cf. Capital
I, Ch. 4: The General Formula for Capital,
p 247ff) as the formula of merchant capitalism where the commodity already
has achieved its money-form (cf. further chapter II.***). The formula
M-C-M’ just contains the essential contradiction between the proposed
equivalent exchange M-C und the following non-equivalent exchange C-M’. To
clear this specific contradiction Marx writes:
But
commodities are not paid for twice over, once on account of their use-value, and
a second time on account of their value. And though the use-value of a commodity
is more serviceable to the buyer than to its seller, its money-form is more so
to the seller. Would he sell otherwise? (Capital
I, p. 262)
The formation of surplus-value, and
therefore the transformation of money into capital, can consequently be
explained neither by assuming that commodities are sold above their value, nor
by assuming that they are bought at less than their value. (Ibid.,
p. 263)
That is,
in equivalence exchange no general gains of surplus-value C-M’ can be achieved
by sale. Again Marx:
We
have shown that surplus-value cannot arise from circulation, and therefore that,
for to be formed, something must take place in the background which is not
visible in the circulation itself. (…) The commodity owner can create value by
his labour, but he cannot create values which can valorize themselves. He can
increase the value of his commodity by adding fresh labour, and therefore more
value, to the value in hand, by making leather into boots, for example. (Ibid., p. 268)
To
understand the production of surplus-value we therefore besides the circulation
sphere have to include the production sphere so that the circulation sphere must
be completed with some processes outside itself. These are, on the one hand,
different yet in the case of a real capitalist economy both necessary and
inseparable. To propose this contradiction at the end of chapter 5 Marx argues
in the following way:
Capital
cannot therefore arise from circulation, and it is equally impossible for it to
arise apart from circulation. It must have its origin both in circulation and
not in circulation.
We therefore have a double result.
The transformation of money in capital has
to be developed on the basis of the immanent laws of exchange of commodities, in
such a way that the starting-point is the exchange of equivalents. The
money-owner, who is as yet only a capitalist in larval form, must buy his
commodities at their value, sell them at their value, and yet at the end of the
process withdraw more value from circulation than he threw into it at the
beginning. His emergence as a butterfly must, and yet must not, take place in
the sphere of circulation. These are the conditions of the problem. Hic
Rhodus, hic salta! (Capital I, pp.
268-69)
In fact,
Marx here presents us for even two affirmative paradoxes derived form the market
function M-C-M’, where the first exchange M-C is based on equivalence (eq
by buying), the other one based the non-equivalence of C-M’ (~eq
by selling) because this extra value can only be the result of some production.
So this market exchange (Exch) is
descriptively characterised by the affirmative paradox
!Exch/Î(eq
& ~eq); these opposed predicatives
can as such only be unified by the market function based partly on the
circulation sphere as such where exchange is done value-equivalently (eq),
partly on the production sphere where labour-power is generating new value, so
that the produced commodities now have more value than their production cost (~eq) (this also expressed in the contradiction between value and
price). These moments of the exchange function taken together gives us the
economical term of un-decidedness ØExch/Îeq Ù ØExch/Î~eq .
These two contradictions implicate each other and are unified in the market
action using money:
(5a)
!Exch/Î(eq & ~eq) Û
ØExch/Îeq Ù
ØExch/Î~eq .
The
second affirmative paradox is based on the productive labour function which
shall be more thoroughly analysed below. Alone based on the functions of the
market, however, there is no definite logical solution of the problem of this
logical un-decidedness. Therefore Marx seeks a ne social moment which as such,
but again “does not abolish these contradictions, but rather provides the form
within they have room to move” (p. 198).
4. Introducing
Labour-power
Therefore, on the very first page of chapter 6 Marx follows this contradiction
up by introducing exactly a new “commodity” to unify its opposites, that is,
a “commodity” with the specific capacity of creation new value. This “commodity”,
the “labour-power” introduced as the cause of this value difference at the
same time distinguishes between the functioning of the market, the circulation
sphere and that of the workshop, the production sphere; and again, by doing this
it also unites these spheres in such a way that we could transform Marx’s
merchant capital formula M-C-M’ into
M-L-M’ (L for “labour-power”). This makes it possible to us also to
change formula 5a into that of the function of “labour-power” when realising
production:
(5b)
!L/Î(eq
& ~eq) Û ØL/Îeq Ù
ØL/Î~eq .
Here in
his Capital Marx in fact has
introduced a quite new scenario to illustrate the essential moment of this very
capitalist “revolution”:
…
our friend the money-owner must be lucky enough to find within the sphere of
circulation, on the market, a commodity whose use-value possess the peculiar
property of being a source of value, whose actual consumption is therefore
itself an objectification [Vergegenständlichung]
of labour, hence a creation of value. The possessor of money does find such a
special commodity on the market: the capacity for labour [Arbeitsvermögen], in other words labour-power [Arbeitskraft]. (Capital I,
p. 270)[2]*****
We mean by labour-power, or labour-capacity, the aggregate of those
mental and physical capabilities existing in the physical form, the living
personality, of a human being, capabilities which he sets in motion whenever he
produces a use-value of any kind. (Ibid.,
p. 270)
But of
course, to ‘find such a special commodity’ (with a self-valorising value!)
with ‘those mental and physical capabilities’
on the market is not
at all so easy as for the butterfly to slip out of the cocoon. The postulated
labourer to be must just be free, free
from money, free from any means, i.e. free as air. But this was in no way the
general situation for the people of that time: everyone was bound up by feudal
rights and demands, on the estates, by the guilds, the church etc. Many of such
dependencies really had to be broken up before the fine new butterfly could
really fly in the air. To break these dependence was a historical process, a
revolution, demanding many hard social and economical struggles, in the first
instance just the struggle for ‘freedom’, exactly ‘freedom’ to enter
into the new capitalist world of freedom, e.g. with the freedom to “sell”
this faculty of labour by entering a wage contract, and so also the
money-owner’s freedom to exploit his worker in order to get maximal profit
from his labour.
So again
we have the contradiction of two amounts of value (V), first that of wages primarily determined by the costs for things
necessary as provisions for the individual worker’s identical reproduction (eq),
secondly that of the higher price achieved by selling the produced things (~eq). That is, through its work this new “commodity” realises a
specific form of exchange (Exch,
formula 5a) in favour of the always value calculating employer. Consequently the
value determinations are again as such involved in these functions un-decided
(note that “value” pr. definition is stated identically constant, at least
in this sense being not self-valorising; cf. part II) what we again might
express by ØV/Îwages Ù
ØV/Î~wages.
Again, “labour-power” as a “commodity” just by production unifies the
value of the agreed wages for reproduction and (as its “self-valorising”
“use-value”[3])
of the value with surplus-value produced in the working process itself and
realised by selling the products: !V/Î(eq
& ~eq). Again we formulate the
dialectical contradiction about value as such under these conditions:
(5c)
!V/Î(eq
& ~eq) Û ØV/Îeq Ù
ØV/Î~eq .
This
formula (5a) demands a serious theoretical comment. You could say that it is
based on an exaggerated quotation of the Marxian text (the owner of commodities
“cannot create values which can valorize themselves,” p. 268), but such a
seemingly simple statement in a yet dialectical text in fact poses an essential
question about the very basis on which the actual theory is built. In the
classical (also Marxian) political economy based primarily on equivalent
exchange value as such is defined abstract identical. In post-classical theory,
however, we find theoreticians basing their basic arguments on fluctuating
interests realised through entering contracts, among others also
labour-contracts. On such a basis it is unavoidable about value to pose the
opposite proposition, at least as a possibility. But in the author’s opinion
this question is not a simple either-or but rather concerns the very dialectics
of all economical theory. The question is rather which of these understandings
is the primary, which the secondary, derivative one, but neither of them as such
being false, and under which historical conditions have they been formulated in
theses ways? This question will be a leading one through the whole book.
5. The Formula of
Capitalist Economy.
The main point is
here expressed by Marx in concentrated form: „Capital cannot therefore arise
from circulation, and it is equally impossible for it to arise apart from
circulation. It must have its origin both in circulation and not in circulation.“
(Capital I, p. 268) That is, Capital (Cap) arises neither from equivalent exchange,
eq , nor apart from
circulation, i.e. from extended production based on non-equivalence (~eq),
in logical terms: ØCap/Îeq Ù
ØCap/Î~eq; in
other words, capital as social-economical formation contains the dialectic contradiction:
(5d)
!Cap/Î(eq & ~eq) Û
ØCap/Îeq Ù
ØCap/Î~eq .
This
‘double result’ means that these two forms of exchange mutually depend on
each other; i.e., they are different but because of the self-valorising value
inseparable, unified in and characterising the capitalist economy. This
‘double result’ can of cause be mirrored, non-circulation ~eq meaning production (prod)
and eq = ~prod,
circulation (market function). That is, the capitalist’s necessary surplus
cannot be generated in the production sphere alone
(ØCap/Îprod)
and (Ù)
neither in the circulation sphere alone
(ØCap/Î~prod);
taken together this reproduces the dialectical contradiction
(6)
!Cap/Î(prod & ~prod)
Û
ØCap/Îprod Ù
ØCap/Î~prod.
This way
of defining capital as production and
circulation (= non-production), !Cap/Î(prod
& circ) or !Cap/Î(prod
& ~prod), might seem
un-necessarily abstract. We e.g could have taken the categories in the reversed
order and one after the other: (this specific form of) Production is capitalist (!Prod/Îcap), and analogously (this specific form of) Circulation is capitalist (!Circ/Îcap).
This would have described two different forms of capitalist action – and at
once indicated that these concepts both are more general than capitalism itself!
Such descriptions could certainly have told us a lot about the predicatives
“capital” too, but thereby not only distinguished Production
from Circulation but rather definitely
separated them from each other (connected only by their identical predicatives).
Thereby we also would have cancelled every possibility of grasping their inner
dialectics and omitted to reveal the deepest and most essential dynamics of the
predicative itself, the capital. However, at issue here is exactly the
inseparability of these social functions, i.e. their non-existence as paradox
capitalist predicatives in isolation (mind you, under the condition of
preservation of the capital as such) and so to define the main capitalist
dialectics, which just is the central issue of this introducing chapter.
6. Labour-power again.
Above we cited Marx (p. 270) for saying that “our friend the money-owner must
be lucky enough to find within the sphere of circulation, on the market [in the
sense of the labour market], a commodity whose use-value possess the peculiar
property of being a source of value, whose actual consumption is therefore
itself an objectification [Vergegenstandlichung] of labour, hence a creation of value.”
‘Find(ing it) within the sphere of circulation, on the market’ means just
being able to ‘buy’ it to its “value” of production (eq
here transformed into the identical monetary measure of the “value”
[p]), the “use-value” of which,
however, ‘possesses the peculiar property of being a source of value, whose
actual consumption is therefore itself … a creation of value’, this again
monetarily determined; call therefore this growth of value (by self-valorisation!)
~eq the monetarily measured
p-negation [~p] .
In this way the so-called “labour-power” in the sense of “living labour”
(L) over time again realises this
un-decidedness of the dialectical contradiction
(6a)
!L/Î([p]
& [~p]) Û
ØL/Î[p] Ù
ØL/Î[~p].
Here the
unifying element in the original form of M-C-M’ (cf. formula 5a), the
“commodity” labour-power L
in fact replaces the commodity C as
defined by money
(6b)
!C/Î([p] & [~p]) Û
ØC/Î[p]
Ù ØC/Î[~p].
This
comparison makes production analogue to market exchange, i.e. again making
labour, the “faculty” or “capacity” of labour, again the
“labour-power”[4]
a kind of commodity but with this curious form of value. The obvious similarity
of the two formulae for resp. L
and C easily explains that
“labour-power” has been seen as a member of the genus commodities. The only
new in these last formulae is that they are based on measured quantities, as
such being rather arithmetic than logic. The essential point in this comparison
is, that the exchange of commodities is a quite formal transaction but on the
contrary production is a real, material function immediately necessary for all
social life as such.
So, as
the essential moment of the capitalist economy we have stated “labour-power”
and its “value” as logically and arithmetically un-decided. Matter is that
this elementary moment of each individual life is produced by natural metabolism
in the body itself depending on consumption of food stuffs and other necessities
themselves produced by metabolically realised labour of other individuals like
themselves by extended production, in fact the general conditions of all life at
all. Only under the condition of private property of money and valued means of
production and ther things this will realise the specific capitalist economy and
life style.
At the
same time we observe that in the course of this capital process our human
individual as a worker somehow “found” on the market is constantly changing
his individual subjectivity. Installed by the employer’s machines and other
means of production he was proposed lacking any specified personality[5]***
(lacking any personal interest in the working process etc.) beside his simple
awareness (“a”-subjectivity, cf.
Part II. ***) necessary to carry out what he was ordered to fully subjected to
the demands and control of his employer. But after the agreed period of working
time and he had received his wages he in a quite radical way changed this
“personality” (cf. Orlando Patterson’s discussion below), now being a
“free” person in every respect disposing over his own property (thereby
realising “q”-subjectivity). So
when he wanted he “freely” might enter into a new labour contract to take up
his bound work for his old employer (or someone else) to earn new wages.
So
we again find an affirmative
paradox of the subjective, ideal “a”-moment
and the objective, non-subjective moment of capitalism, the privately
owned means of production “m” (m = ~a). This can be
expressed as usual by the logical un-decidedness of ØProd/Îa
Ù
ØProd/Î~a ,
the unifying element of which under capitalist conditions is the real
“labour-power” L, here expressed
in its product form a
∙m = f , just as “power”
or even “force” [Kraft] (!).
So we again can characterise the capitalistic production in this twofold way:
(7a)
!Prod/Î(a
& ~a) Û
ØProd/Îa
Ù
Ø
Prod/Î~a
(7b)
!L/Î(a
& ~a) Û
ØL/Îa
Ù
ØL/Î~a
.
7. Un-decidedness and
Fragility. Thereby
we also indicate the essential antagonism between the social bearers of the “a”-subjectivity,
the workers, the proletariat, and the private owners of the means of production “m”,
the capitalists with their “q”-subjectivity
(note the essential reservation to this characteristic made in A6 above). With
the last bi-implications (formulae 7a and b) we have dialectically defined the
capitalism as an economical formation based on the private property to the
socially essential material and economical means in opposition to the
productively involved moments of subjectivity. On the other hand we understand
that affirmative paradoxes as such in the last instance always have an ephemeral
form of existence. As mentioned, these paradoxical existences necessarily have
to be supported by every means; the thingly existence e.g. of the commodity is
not enough, commodities unsold are simply waste, and this dialectics will
steadily be influenced by the economic circumstances. Will the difficulties grow
massively the functions of the capitalist society will be seriously interrupted
and itself as such be gravely threatened (crisis).
Such
situations would provoke strong fear to the employers and capitalists for losing
their traditional room for moving their property, resp. for losing their means
of profit-giving production etc. This, of course, would not mean that basic
capacities of producing and circulation as such would be cancelled, only that
the elementary productive conjunction of subjective and objective, ideal and
material moments had to be organised on new technological, economical and legal
basis, that is, new forms of social, economic, etc. action would then even be
changing the formal determinations of the social activities as such, even
changing the very human interests and so eventually leading to a new,
post-capitalist revolution realising new dialectic contradictions.
[1]
In Peter Ruben: Dialektik
und Arbeit der Philosophie, Pahl Rugenstein Verlag, Köln 1978, pp.
117-145 (transl. R.S.).
[2]
We notice here a remarkable terminological ambivalence: “capacity for labour [Arbeitsvermögen],
in other words labour-power [Arbeitskraft]”
and again: “labour-power, or labour-capacity.” But a “capacity” is
no “power”. We shall return to this ambivalence below (§A6
here and ***)
[3]
The expression ~eq
also indicates, the use-values (unlike values) in general cannot be
determined (measured) numerically.
[4]
We observe here a contradiction by calling both
“faculty (or the capacity) of labour”, “labour-power” and “living
labour” commodities. This contradiction, however, will be cancelled in a
later paragraph of this book, see II.***.
[5]
Cf. §***